April 23, 2016
This game was invented by John Maynard Keynes. Suppose that you hold a stock and the price is rising. However, you believe that the stock price is too high to be justified by the value of the company. You want to sell it, but you would like to wait until the price is as close to the peak as possible i.e. you want to get out of the market just before all the other investors do.
How will other investors act? How will you respond to that?
There was a newspaper in England, where players had to guess which picture other players would like most (guessing another person’s actions). Keynes likened investing to this, it’s not only what you think about the stock, but also what other people are thinking.
In the stylized version:
What would be your strategy? What will other players do? What will you do in response?
Each player chooses their optimal response called the Nash Equilibrium
Suppose that a player believes that the average play will be (this includes their own integer). That player’s optimal strateegy is to say the closest integer to .
Since by definition, the optimal strategy of any player has to be no more than 67. But if is no more than 67, then the optimal strategy of any player has to be no more than . This continues on, multiplying each guess by .
If you keep iterating, you get that the unique Nash equilibrium of this game is for every player to announce 1! In this case, everyone ties and the winner is chosen at random. This is called a stable point
If you try to deviate from this answer, you’d be higher than the average and be guaranteed to lose.
Notice that the Nash Equilibrium works if you believe that everyone can understand and reason through it. If not, you’d be better off naming a higher number.
Now suppose you get to see the results and play again. You would anticipate that everyone would shift their expectations to be lower.
In the second chance, more people move towards the equilibrium. As you increase the number of chances, the graph converges closer to the Nash Equilibrium
Should we expect equilibria to be played? Should we expect non-equilibria to be played?
We should expect non-equilibria to not be stable (i.e. if players see and understand it, we should expect them to move away from the equilibrium)
We saw exactly this in the second round of the game above. We should expect non-equilibria to vanish over time, but they must be learned and players must evolve.
If you know what everyone else will do, it will be easy to pick your own actions. Using the notation from earlier, let:
i.e. the action sequence of everyone except you (you are player ). Then, the entire action profile is really . With this notation, the formal definition of the best response is
However, in reality, no agent knows what the others will do. In this case, we look for stable action profiles.
We say that is a “pure strategy” Nash Equilibrium if:
Suppose we have the following payoff matrix:
This game has a dominant strategy to defect no matter what the other prisoner does. This means that the other player will do the same. Therefore is the Nash equilibrium.
Suppose we have the following payoff matrix:
Suppose you and another person are walking towards each other on a sidewalk. If you co-ordinate, you will be fine, but if you don’t, you will collide. In this case there are two nash equilibria: and .
Suppose we have the following payoff matrix:
Here we have two pure-strategy Nash Equilibria. If one player wants to go to , the other player would be better off choosing , and conversely with . The best response is to go to the movie selected by the other party.
Consider the following payoff matrix:
What is a pure strategy Nash equilibrium here? Suppose player 1 picks heads, then player 2 will pick tail. If player 2 picks tails, then player 1 will pick tails.
The best responses follow a cycle, and therefore there is NO pure strategy Nash Equilibrium here.